Exploration 2: Order of elements
November 11, 2023.So, we can ask an arbitrary group many questions. What are its subgroups? What relations exist on elements of ? Which elements commute with which?
But given only a single arbitrary element , we suddenly run out of interesting questions to ask. We already know the inverse is . We already know we can take its product with itself to get elements like , , etc. But interesting facts like whether or is the identity element, and what subgroup generates, all depend on knowing one thing: what is the order of ?
The order of an element is the least positive integer for which , and is denoted . If taking powers of never results in , we say that is infinite.
If we know the order of , then we can deduce almost every interesting property of . For instance, means is the identity. If , then generates (and thus is cyclic). It turns out the order of decides so much, that if you are given any information about alone, you can probably translate it to a statement about the order of (and vice versa).
Here’s an example:
Given that the order of is , we know that is the lowest positive power of equal to the identity . Then generates the subgroup , which has exactly elements, thus .
In this section, we learn how to calculate the order of elements.
For a finite group, the main way to calculate the order of an element is by applying a corollary of Lagrange’s Theorem.
Recall that an element can generate a subgroup . Since is a subgroup of a finite group, apply Lagrange’s Theorem to show that divides . But , so also divides .
This theorem restricts the possible orders of elements to divisors of the group’s order . For instance, if , then elements in can only have orders . In fact, the following theorem says that elements must exist for the prime orders, :
- Consider , which is the direct product of with itself times. Its elements are -tuples of elements from . We will proceed by a counting argument, first by defining a set and providing two ways to count .
- Let be the subset of where taking the product of all components in the -tuple gives the identity . That is,
- To find , note that the first components of each -tuple in can be chosen arbitrarily from (finite) , but the final component must be the inverse of the product of the first components. Therefore, . Given that is divisible by a prime , we have for some . Then .
- Any permutation of a -tuple in is a -tuple in , since order doesn’t matter when we take product. Then consider two -tuples equivalent when one is a cyclic permutation of the other. This divides into equivalence classes of two sizes: elements of the form belong in an equivalence class of size , while any other equivalence class must be of size because is prime.
- Towards contradiction, assume that is the only equivalence class of size . Then let be the number of equivalence classes of size , so that .
- Therefore . Taking mod gives , contradiction.
- Therefore there must be more equivalence classes of size , implying that contains some nontrivial . Membership in implies , so is an element of order .
If your group is a direct product, then you can deduce the order of its elements via the order of each component.
Proving this for is enough to prove the theorem by induction. Let and , so that and . Then implies is a multiple of both and . Since order of an element is the least such multiple, the order of must be .
In this section, we prove facts about subgroup order.
Knowing the order of elements lets you identify subgroups. For instance, if is order , then is a cyclic subgroup of order . From there we can construct more interesting subgroups.
Recall that for subgroups and , we have .
This tells us that having trivial intersection is desirable for subgroups. So when do subgroups have trivial intersection?
- The intersection of two subgroups is a subgroup of both: and .
- By Lagrange, is a divisor of both and .
- Since and are coprime, their only shared divisor is , so , and therefore .
There are two cases: either or for some prime .
- If have different prime orders, then they have coprime orders and by the previous theorem the intersection is trivial.
- Otherwise, for some prime . By Lagrange, is a divisor of both and . Since is prime, is either or . It can’t be since are distinct. So the intersection is trivial.
In this section, we determine the structure of groups based on their order.
One application of order is to determine whether a subset is a conjugacy class.
- The key is knowing that, given ,
- This shows that the order of is at most the order of .
- We can show that the order of cannot be lower than the order of by contradiction.
- Suppose , implying . Then which is not possible since .
- Therefore the order of every is exactly the order of .
Because of this,
Knowing the order of a given group sometimes lets you identify it outright. Here are some examples:
- Since is prime, and therefore there is a non-identity element with order .
- By Lagrange’s Theorem, the order of every element divides . Since is prime and , the order of can only be .
- But that means generates , therefore is cyclic.
- The center must be a subgroup, which by Lagrange’s Theorem must have order equal to one of .
- Since is a -group and therefore its center has order divisible by , the center of cannot be order .
- If the center is order , then implies is cyclic. But that means is abelian.
- If the center is order , it can only be the entire group which makes abelian by definition.
Recall that a group is abelian iff the quotient group is cyclic, and that a group is cyclic if it has prime order. Thus if has prime order, then is abelian.
Again by Lagrange’s Theorem, the order of the center must divide the order of the group , and thus the center can only be of order .
- If the center is order then the group is abelian by definition.
- If the center is order then the group is centerless by definition.
- Otherwise, the center is prime or , and therefore has prime order or , which makes abelian.
- By Lagrange’s Theorem, implies any element has order dividing , i.e. .
- If every non-identity element was order
then
is abelian, and the set
for any non-identity
is closed and therefore a subgroup of
.
By
Lagrange,
must divide
,
a contradiction. So we must have some
that is order
or order
.
- If exists such that , then generates , so .
- If
exists such that
,
then
is a subgroup of order
.
WTS
.
- is the unique subgroup of order . To see this, consider another subgroup of order . Since and are distinct prime order subgroups, their intersection is trivial. (proof) But then (proof) which is greater than , contradiction.
- Then for non-identity , we know that since is the unique subgroup of order . But since is not identity (), and does not generate (), we must have for every not in .
- Since , as well. This means both and are self-inverse: .
- The group is exactly (isomorphic to) the dihedral group .
In this section, we introduce the exponent of a group.
The exponent of a group is the LCM of the order of every element of the group. The idea is that is the smallest integer that is high enough so that for all . If there is no such integer (because some element has infinite order), the exponent is infinity.
Let’s prove some useful properties of the exponent:
The order of the generator of must be , so the exponent is at least . By Lagrange’s theorem, the order of every element of divides its order , so the exponent is at most . Therefore the exponent is exactly .
- Proving this for is enough to prove the theorem by induction.
- If either of or have infinite exponent, then LCM of their exponents is infinite, which is equal to the exponent of (infinity), and we are done.
- Otherwise, assume or have finite exponents.
- For every of , by definition of exponent, we know that and .
- is the least such that . For the middle equality to hold, must be a multiple of both and . Since needs to be the least such , we have .
This combines the previous two theorems. The exponent of a direct product is the LCM of the exponent of each , which is , thus the above statement follows.
If we take as the generator of each cyclic group, then has order equal to the LCM of the orders of each , i.e. the LCM of all , which is exactly the exponent of .
Since is a direct product of cyclic groups each of order , we have .
- ()
- Since is cyclic, it has a generator of order , where each generates .
- Since the order of a direct product element must be the LCM of the order of each component , we have .
- But then (above) implies . Since the LCM of each is equal to the product of each , the must be pairwise coprime.
- ()
- By the previous proof, there is an element whose order is equal to the exponent of , i.e. the LCM of each . But since each are pairwise coprime, their LCM is equal to their product. That means , which implies generates , so is cyclic.
Exploration 3: Products and quotients